IMAO, the biggest philosophical problem of Quantum Mechanics is the “measurement problem”. According to Quantum Mechanics, “measurement”, or “observation”, collapses the wavefunction of a particle. Particles behave one way when we are looking, and a very different way as soon as we divert our gaze.
(For more background on the quantum measurement problem, see my blog post http://mccomplete.blogspot.de/2012/07/decoherence-and-flying-fish.html .)
It’s almost as if there are two worlds: the visible world and the hidden world.
I want to call attention to two differences between the visible world and the hidden world:
In the visible world, any given particle at any given time is in one, and only one, place. But in the hidden world, at any given time, any given particle can be in more than one place.
The behavior of the hidden world is almost absurd. If a particle is in two places at the same time, it shouldn’t be one particle anymore. It should be two particles. But it isn’t, it’s still only one.
In my arrogant opinion, this is a kind of miracle. In conventional miracles, isolated events defy the laws of nature. But in the quantum miracle, the laws of nature defy the laws of logic.
The hidden world is absurd and miraculous. The visible world, on the other hand, is coherent.
There are miracles happening constantly all around us, but we can’t see them. They’re hidden from us.
Now for the second difference between the visible world and the hidden world:
The hidden world is deterministic and the visible world is nondeterministic. The hidden world is entirely governed by natural law; the visible world is influenced probabilitsically by natural law, but it is, in a sense, chaotic, lawless. So the world behaves lawfully, but the lawfulness is hidden from us. When we look, all we see is lawlessness.
Maybe Divine Providence is like this. Maybe the world is lawful and just, but the lawfulness is hidden. Maybe behind the veil of coherence, good things happen to good people, but when we look, all we see is lawlessness, chance, indifference.
Wednesday, September 5, 2012
Shiluach Haken, Part 2: The Reward for Mitzvot
In the end of Masechet Chullin, the Gemara tells the tragic story of a father who told his young son to climb up a tree and get some eggs. The boy climbed up the tree, sent away the mother bird, lost his footing, and fell to his death.
The boy had performed two mitzvot: honoring his father, and sending away the mother bird. The Torah promises a long life as a reward for both mitzvot.
Elisha ben Abuya declared, “There is no justice and no Judge,” and went off the derech.
Rebbe Akiva declared, “There is no reward for mitzvot in this world, but in the next world, there is reward.”
On the other hand, every morning after the blessings of the Torah, we recite the Mishna of Elu Devarim. Elu devarim says that there are mitzvot that bear fruit in this world, while the principal is saved for us in the next world. (One of the mitzvot listed in Elu Devarim is honoring parents.)
I think that the mitzvot have a component of prudence. Following the mitzvot is often the most responsible way to act. Sometimes the mitzvot good advice about how to act wisely and achieve our own self-interest. For instance, if you do acts of chessed, the recipients will sometimes return the favor, and the members of the community will like you and give you honor and support. The study of Torah pays off in thinking skills and self-control.
But the mitzvot are not all about prudence. The mitzvot have a component that transcends prudence. They have a component of compassion, of honesty, of humility, of yirat Hashem.
Sometimes all these core values overlap with rational self-interest. But since they are distinct values, there is also a set difference, where following the mitzvot is not the best way to optimize for self interest. Thus, burial of the dead is called “chessed shel emet”, because the recipient can never repay you.
When the mitzvot call for self-sacrifice, the reward may be in the next world. When the mitzvot call for prudence, the reward may be(partly) in this world.
Prudence is probabilistic. Statistically speaking, on average, people who honor their parents do better than those who neglect to do so. But prudence gives no guarantees. Tragically, there are those who honor their parents and get hurt nonetheless. Rebbe Akiva teaches us that these people will be rewarded in the world to come.
The boy had performed two mitzvot: honoring his father, and sending away the mother bird. The Torah promises a long life as a reward for both mitzvot.
Elisha ben Abuya declared, “There is no justice and no Judge,” and went off the derech.
Rebbe Akiva declared, “There is no reward for mitzvot in this world, but in the next world, there is reward.”
On the other hand, every morning after the blessings of the Torah, we recite the Mishna of Elu Devarim. Elu devarim says that there are mitzvot that bear fruit in this world, while the principal is saved for us in the next world. (One of the mitzvot listed in Elu Devarim is honoring parents.)
I think that the mitzvot have a component of prudence. Following the mitzvot is often the most responsible way to act. Sometimes the mitzvot good advice about how to act wisely and achieve our own self-interest. For instance, if you do acts of chessed, the recipients will sometimes return the favor, and the members of the community will like you and give you honor and support. The study of Torah pays off in thinking skills and self-control.
But the mitzvot are not all about prudence. The mitzvot have a component that transcends prudence. They have a component of compassion, of honesty, of humility, of yirat Hashem.
Sometimes all these core values overlap with rational self-interest. But since they are distinct values, there is also a set difference, where following the mitzvot is not the best way to optimize for self interest. Thus, burial of the dead is called “chessed shel emet”, because the recipient can never repay you.
When the mitzvot call for self-sacrifice, the reward may be in the next world. When the mitzvot call for prudence, the reward may be(partly) in this world.
Prudence is probabilistic. Statistically speaking, on average, people who honor their parents do better than those who neglect to do so. But prudence gives no guarantees. Tragically, there are those who honor their parents and get hurt nonetheless. Rebbe Akiva teaches us that these people will be rewarded in the world to come.
Wednesday, August 29, 2012
Shiluach Haken, Part One: Save the Pigeons?
What is the rationale behind the mitzvah of shiluach haken, sending away the mother bird?
The Rambam, in "Guide for the Perplexed", explains that we are enjoined to send away the mother bird as an act of compassion, to spare her the anguish of seeing her children taken away for the slaughter.
This approach strikes me as very strange. Is sending away the mother bird really an act of compassion? Does the bird really experience less anguish when she is sent away than when her children are taken before her eyes? Clearly, she is trying to protect her children -- why does it matter whether you send her away or whether you take the children?
The Ramban, in his commentary on the Torah, gives a different explanation. He says that by sending away the mother bird, we are saving the species, even as we are consuming the individuals.
So according to the Ramban, “send away the mother bird” should be understood as “spare the mother bird”. When you find a bird’s nest inhabited by a mother and children, don’t eat all the birds; eat the children, and leave the mother alone.
I like the Ramban’s approach, but I don’t think it should be understood as the expression of a “caretaker” environmentalism, which would enjoin us to protect endangered species for the sake of biodiversity. I think that the reason we are supposed to protect “species” (really, populations) of kosher birds is so that we will be able to go on eating the individuals. We are supposed to send away the mother bird so that she can make more baby birds for us to eat. It’s sustainable hunting, essentially.
Similarly, the original mitzva of "bal tashchit" prohibits cutting down trees under some circumstances, but the prohibition explicitly applies only to trees with human-edible fruit. The Torah is not concerned with botanical diversity, but with sustainable consumption of natural resources. (Thanks to my father for pointing this out!)
The sabbatical year may also be related in part to sustainable farming. The sabbatical year demonstrates the Divine ownership of the land, but it also allows the land to "rest".
Don't get me wrong, though. I don’t mean to say that the Torah is indifferent to the suffering of animals. The Torah clearly cares about animal suffering. That consideration has its own dedicated mitzva, “tzaar baalei chayim”, the prohibition of causing needless suffering to animals. But shiluach haken is not about compassion. It’s about the tragedy of the commons.
For a more thorough treatment of the intellectual history of shiluach haken, please see the wonderful paper by Rabbi Natan Slifkin, available here: http://www.rationalistjudaism.com/2010/08/shiluach-hakein-transformation-of.html
The Rambam, in "Guide for the Perplexed", explains that we are enjoined to send away the mother bird as an act of compassion, to spare her the anguish of seeing her children taken away for the slaughter.
This approach strikes me as very strange. Is sending away the mother bird really an act of compassion? Does the bird really experience less anguish when she is sent away than when her children are taken before her eyes? Clearly, she is trying to protect her children -- why does it matter whether you send her away or whether you take the children?
The Ramban, in his commentary on the Torah, gives a different explanation. He says that by sending away the mother bird, we are saving the species, even as we are consuming the individuals.
So according to the Ramban, “send away the mother bird” should be understood as “spare the mother bird”. When you find a bird’s nest inhabited by a mother and children, don’t eat all the birds; eat the children, and leave the mother alone.
I like the Ramban’s approach, but I don’t think it should be understood as the expression of a “caretaker” environmentalism, which would enjoin us to protect endangered species for the sake of biodiversity. I think that the reason we are supposed to protect “species” (really, populations) of kosher birds is so that we will be able to go on eating the individuals. We are supposed to send away the mother bird so that she can make more baby birds for us to eat. It’s sustainable hunting, essentially.
Similarly, the original mitzva of "bal tashchit" prohibits cutting down trees under some circumstances, but the prohibition explicitly applies only to trees with human-edible fruit. The Torah is not concerned with botanical diversity, but with sustainable consumption of natural resources. (Thanks to my father for pointing this out!)
The sabbatical year may also be related in part to sustainable farming. The sabbatical year demonstrates the Divine ownership of the land, but it also allows the land to "rest".
Don't get me wrong, though. I don’t mean to say that the Torah is indifferent to the suffering of animals. The Torah clearly cares about animal suffering. That consideration has its own dedicated mitzva, “tzaar baalei chayim”, the prohibition of causing needless suffering to animals. But shiluach haken is not about compassion. It’s about the tragedy of the commons.
For a more thorough treatment of the intellectual history of shiluach haken, please see the wonderful paper by Rabbi Natan Slifkin, available here: http://www.rationalistjudaism.com/2010/08/shiluach-hakein-transformation-of.html
Wednesday, August 8, 2012
Empricism with a Formalist Face: A Platonic Dialogue by MC Complete
Stewart: Enough of epistemology. Let’s get down to brass tacks. What is a number?
Daniel: A number is the outcome of a measurement. Take the expression “7 + 5 = 12”. This expression is an empirical prediction (or, if you are a hard core skeptic, an empirical generalization). I could test it by putting seven apples and five oranges in a basket and counting them. Counting is an empirical process that yields the result, 12. The assumption that I started with -- that there are seven apples and five oranges -- means that when I count the apples I get 7, and when I count the oranges I get 5.
Stewart: Hmmm. Interesting, but doesn’t that just beg the question? You said “I get 12” -- but what *is* 12? What do you get?
Daniel: 12 has a written form and an auditory signature, which vary, of course, according to language. It’s a linguistic token.
Stewart: But that’s formalism. I thought that you were an empiricist regarding math.
Daniel: It’s formalism with an empiricist heart, or maybe empiricism with a formalist face. Numbers are linguistic tokens that are the return value of an empirical procedure. Linguistic tokens are sense data, among other things.
Stewart: Interesting that you drew on deductivism in your last post, which is a branch of formalism. I see how you’re advocating a compromise position between formalism and empiricism.
Daniel: Compromise? I prefer to call it The Great Synthesis.
Daniel: A number is the outcome of a measurement. Take the expression “7 + 5 = 12”. This expression is an empirical prediction (or, if you are a hard core skeptic, an empirical generalization). I could test it by putting seven apples and five oranges in a basket and counting them. Counting is an empirical process that yields the result, 12. The assumption that I started with -- that there are seven apples and five oranges -- means that when I count the apples I get 7, and when I count the oranges I get 5.
Stewart: Hmmm. Interesting, but doesn’t that just beg the question? You said “I get 12” -- but what *is* 12? What do you get?
Daniel: 12 has a written form and an auditory signature, which vary, of course, according to language. It’s a linguistic token.
Stewart: But that’s formalism. I thought that you were an empiricist regarding math.
Daniel: It’s formalism with an empiricist heart, or maybe empiricism with a formalist face. Numbers are linguistic tokens that are the return value of an empirical procedure. Linguistic tokens are sense data, among other things.
Stewart: Interesting that you drew on deductivism in your last post, which is a branch of formalism. I see how you’re advocating a compromise position between formalism and empiricism.
Daniel: Compromise? I prefer to call it The Great Synthesis.
The Empiricist Strikes Back: A Platonic Dialogue by MC Complete
Daniel: Don’t get me wrong, Stewart, I’m not a hard core empiricist. But they empiricists were right about some things.
Stewart: What do you have in mind?
Daniel: Math, for example.
Stewart: Really? You think math is the crown jewel of empricism? Very well then, I’ll play your game. Tell me, Daniel, what are we to make of the Euclidean postulate that between any two points one can draw a straight line?
Daniel: What’s the problem? Take out a sheet of paper and a pencil, make two dots anywhere, then connect them. Bang! Straight line.
Stewart: But it’s not a breadthless line.
Daniel: Breadthless? Who said anything about breadthless?
Stewart: John Stuart Mill. He said that lines are “limit concepts”.
Daniel: Yeah, that whole “limit concepts” strategy was a big mistake. Lines aren’t limit concepts. They’re just very thin.
Stewart: And what about the postulate that all lines can be bisected by a perpendicular line?
Daniel: That’s empirical too -- as long as you interpret it correctly. What it really means is that all sufficiently long lines can be bisected that way. Between you and me, if a line is really too short to be bisected, it’s not much of a line, is it? It’s more of a dot, wouldn’t you say?
Stewart: And what about heartbeats? How can you empirically justify the proposition that 2 heartbeats plus 3 heartbeats equals 5 heartbeats?
Daniel: That’s easy. Take an MP3 file with 5 heartbeats. I can play that file and count 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 -- and then I can play the file again and count 1, 2, 1, 2, 3.
Stewart: And what is 500 red marbles plus 500 blue marbles?
Daniel: Oh, about 1000 marbles, I’d say.
Stewart: “About” 1000? You seem to have anticipated my line of argument.
Daniel: You were going to say that if I counted the marbles, I probably wouldn’t come up with exactly 1000.
Stewart: Yes, that’s exactly what I was going to say. How did you know?
Daniel: First of all, I read your book. Second of all, I’m the one writing the dialogue. Anyway, here’s my point. Arithmetic with big numbers, like geometry and arithmetic with continuous quantities, is only approximate. I mean you have to reinterpret the propositions to be approximate propositions. So we usually say 500 + 500 = 1000, but what we really mean is 500 + 500 is about equal to 1000.
Stewart: And what about infinity?
Daniel: Infinity? What’s the big deal with infinity?
Stewart: Well, imagine a universe with only 100 objects.
Daniel: OK.
Stewart: In such a universe, is the proposition “75 * 2 = 150” true or false?
Daniel: Good question. First of all, let’s agree that the proposition “75 * 2 = 150” is the outcome of applying the arithmetic algorithms.
Stewart: OK.
Daniel: And the arithmetic algorithms themselves work in the Hundredverse -- for all actual quantities that we can test.
Stewart: OK.
Daniel: So the expression “75 * 2 = 150” is kind of an “if then” statement -- it means that if we had a set of 75 objects that we could double, we’d expect the result to be 150. Since there is no such set in the Hundredverse, the “if” part is not satisfiable.
Stewart: That sounds kind of like deductivism.
Daniel: I think it is a kind of deductivism, but traditional deductivism is agnostic about the justification for the axioms. I think the justification is empirical.
Stewart: And what is that justification? Enumerative induction? The web of knowledge?
Daniel: Neither. The justification for math is more or less the same as the justification for physics: experiment.
Stewart: But mathematicians don’t do experiments.
Daniel: They don’t need to. The physicists do the experiments for them. In order to predict the outcome of a physics experiment you need physics *and* math -- so the success of the experiment justifies both kinds of inputs.
Stewart: And what about mathematical induction? And the completeness axiom?
Daniel: I’m not smart enough to know if these mathematical tools are used in physics or not, but I would have to go with Quine here. If they are used in physics, they are justified by the experiments that test them. If not, they are toys and curiosities. Of course, sometimes a caterpillar of pleasure can become a butterfly of knowledge. This happens in physics too, for example in the case of relativity.
Stewart: And you would also go with Quine in rejecting the certainty and necessity of mathematics?
Daniel: Yes. As you say in your account of Quineinism, “We cannot conceve of 7 + 5 being anything other than 12. This, however, is a psychological feature of human beings”.
Stewart: What do you have in mind?
Daniel: Math, for example.
Stewart: Really? You think math is the crown jewel of empricism? Very well then, I’ll play your game. Tell me, Daniel, what are we to make of the Euclidean postulate that between any two points one can draw a straight line?
Daniel: What’s the problem? Take out a sheet of paper and a pencil, make two dots anywhere, then connect them. Bang! Straight line.
Stewart: But it’s not a breadthless line.
Daniel: Breadthless? Who said anything about breadthless?
Stewart: John Stuart Mill. He said that lines are “limit concepts”.
Daniel: Yeah, that whole “limit concepts” strategy was a big mistake. Lines aren’t limit concepts. They’re just very thin.
Stewart: And what about the postulate that all lines can be bisected by a perpendicular line?
Daniel: That’s empirical too -- as long as you interpret it correctly. What it really means is that all sufficiently long lines can be bisected that way. Between you and me, if a line is really too short to be bisected, it’s not much of a line, is it? It’s more of a dot, wouldn’t you say?
Stewart: And what about heartbeats? How can you empirically justify the proposition that 2 heartbeats plus 3 heartbeats equals 5 heartbeats?
Daniel: That’s easy. Take an MP3 file with 5 heartbeats. I can play that file and count 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 -- and then I can play the file again and count 1, 2, 1, 2, 3.
Stewart: And what is 500 red marbles plus 500 blue marbles?
Daniel: Oh, about 1000 marbles, I’d say.
Stewart: “About” 1000? You seem to have anticipated my line of argument.
Daniel: You were going to say that if I counted the marbles, I probably wouldn’t come up with exactly 1000.
Stewart: Yes, that’s exactly what I was going to say. How did you know?
Daniel: First of all, I read your book. Second of all, I’m the one writing the dialogue. Anyway, here’s my point. Arithmetic with big numbers, like geometry and arithmetic with continuous quantities, is only approximate. I mean you have to reinterpret the propositions to be approximate propositions. So we usually say 500 + 500 = 1000, but what we really mean is 500 + 500 is about equal to 1000.
Stewart: And what about infinity?
Daniel: Infinity? What’s the big deal with infinity?
Stewart: Well, imagine a universe with only 100 objects.
Daniel: OK.
Stewart: In such a universe, is the proposition “75 * 2 = 150” true or false?
Daniel: Good question. First of all, let’s agree that the proposition “75 * 2 = 150” is the outcome of applying the arithmetic algorithms.
Stewart: OK.
Daniel: And the arithmetic algorithms themselves work in the Hundredverse -- for all actual quantities that we can test.
Stewart: OK.
Daniel: So the expression “75 * 2 = 150” is kind of an “if then” statement -- it means that if we had a set of 75 objects that we could double, we’d expect the result to be 150. Since there is no such set in the Hundredverse, the “if” part is not satisfiable.
Stewart: That sounds kind of like deductivism.
Daniel: I think it is a kind of deductivism, but traditional deductivism is agnostic about the justification for the axioms. I think the justification is empirical.
Stewart: And what is that justification? Enumerative induction? The web of knowledge?
Daniel: Neither. The justification for math is more or less the same as the justification for physics: experiment.
Stewart: But mathematicians don’t do experiments.
Daniel: They don’t need to. The physicists do the experiments for them. In order to predict the outcome of a physics experiment you need physics *and* math -- so the success of the experiment justifies both kinds of inputs.
Stewart: And what about mathematical induction? And the completeness axiom?
Daniel: I’m not smart enough to know if these mathematical tools are used in physics or not, but I would have to go with Quine here. If they are used in physics, they are justified by the experiments that test them. If not, they are toys and curiosities. Of course, sometimes a caterpillar of pleasure can become a butterfly of knowledge. This happens in physics too, for example in the case of relativity.
Stewart: And you would also go with Quine in rejecting the certainty and necessity of mathematics?
Daniel: Yes. As you say in your account of Quineinism, “We cannot conceve of 7 + 5 being anything other than 12. This, however, is a psychological feature of human beings”.
Tuesday, July 24, 2012
The Dinosaurs of Copenhagen: A Platonic Dialogue by MC Complete
(Note: if you don’t have some familiarity with quantum mechanics and the two most popular interpretations -- Copenhagen and Many Worlds -- you may have trouble following this post. Have a look at my post, Decoherence and Flying Fish.)
Hugh: Very clever Niels. But what about the dinosaurs?
Niels: The dinosaurs?
Hugh: You know what I mean. If the only thing that’s real is scientific measurements, doesn’t that imply that the dinosaurs are not real? No living, breathing dinosaur ever entered a laboratory. And if dinosaurs are not real, then what are all those bones doing there? And what about the Big Bang?
Niels: Good question, Hugh. Did you ever read MC Complete’s blog post, Science does not make Predictions?
Hugh: Of course. It was very clever, but it was written from a philosophical point of view that I can’t identify with.
Niels: What do you mean?
Hugh: Well, it was written from a skeptical point of view. It was based on the philosophy of David Hume, who rejected matter, memory and induction. I’m a realist, so skeptical philosophy, while sometimes interesting, is not personally relevant to me.
Niels: I think you misunderstood MC Complete’s point.
Hugh: Really? What was his point, then?
Niels: When Descartes said “I think therefore I am”, was he denying the existence of the outside world?
Hugh: Of course not. Descartes was a realist.
Niels: Ultimately, Descartes was a realist, but he started from a very solipsistic foundation. When he said “I think therefore I am”, was he affirming the existence of the outside world?
Hugh: No, not really. His affirmation of realism was yet to come.
Niels: So at the point in his argument when he said “I think therefore I am”, he was agnostic on the existence of the outside world. At that point, he neither affirmed it or denied it.
Hugh: OK.
Niels: So that was MC Complete’s point. He posited a minimalist, conservative, lightweight ontology, one where memory exists, but it may not be a true record of anything, and one where matter may or may not exist, and induction may or may not be valid.
Hugh: OK.
Niels: And he showed that given the minimalist ontology, we still have math and science. Science is a generalization over the apparent past.
Hugh: So you’re saying that the minimalist ontology of the “Predictions” post neither affirms nor denies realism.
Niels: Exactly. MC Complete’s point was not to reject realism, but rather to show that science does not need realism. It makes no commitment to realism and does not depend on it.
Hugh: And what about the dinosaurs?
Niels: Exactly. What do you think MC Complete would say about the dinosaurs?
Hugh: Well, I suppose he’d be agnostic about the dinosaurs. He’d say that dinosaur bones are a feature of the apparent past, but did actual dinosaurs exist? Who knows. Science doesn’t need real dinosaurs.
Niels: Exactly. I can generalize over the apparent past by positing virtual dinosaurs, but the actual existence of dinosaurs is the domain of philosophy and metaphysics.
Hugh: And that’s your answer about the dinosaurs too?
Niels: Yes. MC Complete thought he was very clever with his declaration that science is generalizations over the apparent past, but really he was just clarifying the Copenhagen approach to science. In fact, Werner Heisenberg came very close to MC Complete’s “Predictions” post when he said: “Physics must confine itself to the description of the relationship between perceptions.”
Hugh: Very clever, Niels. But there’s still one thing that I don’t understand.
Niels: And what would that be?
Hugh: You said that the Copenhagen philosophy of science is noncommittal towards more expansive ontologies.
Niels: Yes.
Hugh: So why do you reject the Many Worlds interpretation?
Niels: I don’t.
Hugh: Wait a minute. In real life, you *did* reject it.
Niels: Yes, I did. It’s too bad I never got to meet MC Complete. I’m sure he’d have shown me that Copenhagen and Many Worlds are not mutually exclusive. In fact, you and I have been talking past each other all these years. Copenhagen is philosophy of science, and all other interpretations, such as Many Worlds, are metaphysics. All I can say is this: before quantum mechanics, if you wanted to be a realist, all you had to do was adopt a few extra axioms, what I like to call the dogmas of common sense. After quantum mechanics, if you want to be a realist, you have a lot of explaining to do.
Hugh: The Many Worlds interpretation does provide an explanation.
Niels: Indeed it does. And maybe it’s correct. Who knows?
Hugh: Very clever Niels. But what about the dinosaurs?
Niels: The dinosaurs?
Hugh: You know what I mean. If the only thing that’s real is scientific measurements, doesn’t that imply that the dinosaurs are not real? No living, breathing dinosaur ever entered a laboratory. And if dinosaurs are not real, then what are all those bones doing there? And what about the Big Bang?
Niels: Good question, Hugh. Did you ever read MC Complete’s blog post, Science does not make Predictions?
Hugh: Of course. It was very clever, but it was written from a philosophical point of view that I can’t identify with.
Niels: What do you mean?
Hugh: Well, it was written from a skeptical point of view. It was based on the philosophy of David Hume, who rejected matter, memory and induction. I’m a realist, so skeptical philosophy, while sometimes interesting, is not personally relevant to me.
Niels: I think you misunderstood MC Complete’s point.
Hugh: Really? What was his point, then?
Niels: When Descartes said “I think therefore I am”, was he denying the existence of the outside world?
Hugh: Of course not. Descartes was a realist.
Niels: Ultimately, Descartes was a realist, but he started from a very solipsistic foundation. When he said “I think therefore I am”, was he affirming the existence of the outside world?
Hugh: No, not really. His affirmation of realism was yet to come.
Niels: So at the point in his argument when he said “I think therefore I am”, he was agnostic on the existence of the outside world. At that point, he neither affirmed it or denied it.
Hugh: OK.
Niels: So that was MC Complete’s point. He posited a minimalist, conservative, lightweight ontology, one where memory exists, but it may not be a true record of anything, and one where matter may or may not exist, and induction may or may not be valid.
Hugh: OK.
Niels: And he showed that given the minimalist ontology, we still have math and science. Science is a generalization over the apparent past.
Hugh: So you’re saying that the minimalist ontology of the “Predictions” post neither affirms nor denies realism.
Niels: Exactly. MC Complete’s point was not to reject realism, but rather to show that science does not need realism. It makes no commitment to realism and does not depend on it.
Hugh: And what about the dinosaurs?
Niels: Exactly. What do you think MC Complete would say about the dinosaurs?
Hugh: Well, I suppose he’d be agnostic about the dinosaurs. He’d say that dinosaur bones are a feature of the apparent past, but did actual dinosaurs exist? Who knows. Science doesn’t need real dinosaurs.
Niels: Exactly. I can generalize over the apparent past by positing virtual dinosaurs, but the actual existence of dinosaurs is the domain of philosophy and metaphysics.
Hugh: And that’s your answer about the dinosaurs too?
Niels: Yes. MC Complete thought he was very clever with his declaration that science is generalizations over the apparent past, but really he was just clarifying the Copenhagen approach to science. In fact, Werner Heisenberg came very close to MC Complete’s “Predictions” post when he said: “Physics must confine itself to the description of the relationship between perceptions.”
Hugh: Very clever, Niels. But there’s still one thing that I don’t understand.
Niels: And what would that be?
Hugh: You said that the Copenhagen philosophy of science is noncommittal towards more expansive ontologies.
Niels: Yes.
Hugh: So why do you reject the Many Worlds interpretation?
Niels: I don’t.
Hugh: Wait a minute. In real life, you *did* reject it.
Niels: Yes, I did. It’s too bad I never got to meet MC Complete. I’m sure he’d have shown me that Copenhagen and Many Worlds are not mutually exclusive. In fact, you and I have been talking past each other all these years. Copenhagen is philosophy of science, and all other interpretations, such as Many Worlds, are metaphysics. All I can say is this: before quantum mechanics, if you wanted to be a realist, all you had to do was adopt a few extra axioms, what I like to call the dogmas of common sense. After quantum mechanics, if you want to be a realist, you have a lot of explaining to do.
Hugh: The Many Worlds interpretation does provide an explanation.
Niels: Indeed it does. And maybe it’s correct. Who knows?
Decoherence and Flying Fish
“I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics.” -- Richard Feynman
We usually assume that at any given time, all objects have a definite location. For example, last week I was in the US; this week I am in Israel. But quantum mechanics postulates that microscopic particles can be in two (or more) places at once. So if I was a microscopic particle, I could be 25% in the US and 75% percent in Israel, etc.
Now here comes the weird part. When somebody looks at (or observes, or measures) the particle, the particle chooses one of these locations, at random. So if I was a microscopic particle who was 10% in Tel Aviv and 90% in Jerusalem, and then you called my cell phone to see where I am, there would be a 10% chance that I would be in Tel Aviv and a %90 chance that I’d be in Jerusalem.
You might ask, what is the difference between saying that a given Libicki Boson is 10% in Tel Aviv and %90 in Jerusalem, and saying that we simply don’t know where it is, but we would bet 9 to 1 that it’s in Jerusalem? It turns out that there is a big difference. The particle’s “superposition”, as it is called, is responsible for what is known as the interference effect, which in turn is responsible for some of the wavelike properties of microscopic particles. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Double_slit_experiment
In my arrogant opinion, one of the most important aspects of quantum mechanics that needs to be pinned down is what counts as an observation or a measurement. Microscopic particles are in many places at once, but if we look, they appear in only one of these places. This choice of position then affects the future motion of the particle. So the critical question is: what counts as looking?
The branch of quantum mechanics that tries to pin this down is called “decoherence”. I tried reading about decoherence and it went way over my head. There was a lot of math. After five minutes of absolute confusion, I gave up and watched a YouTube video:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gAjzH0vWSIA
Flying fish! How cool is that?
We usually assume that at any given time, all objects have a definite location. For example, last week I was in the US; this week I am in Israel. But quantum mechanics postulates that microscopic particles can be in two (or more) places at once. So if I was a microscopic particle, I could be 25% in the US and 75% percent in Israel, etc.
Now here comes the weird part. When somebody looks at (or observes, or measures) the particle, the particle chooses one of these locations, at random. So if I was a microscopic particle who was 10% in Tel Aviv and 90% in Jerusalem, and then you called my cell phone to see where I am, there would be a 10% chance that I would be in Tel Aviv and a %90 chance that I’d be in Jerusalem.
You might ask, what is the difference between saying that a given Libicki Boson is 10% in Tel Aviv and %90 in Jerusalem, and saying that we simply don’t know where it is, but we would bet 9 to 1 that it’s in Jerusalem? It turns out that there is a big difference. The particle’s “superposition”, as it is called, is responsible for what is known as the interference effect, which in turn is responsible for some of the wavelike properties of microscopic particles. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Double_slit_experiment
In my arrogant opinion, one of the most important aspects of quantum mechanics that needs to be pinned down is what counts as an observation or a measurement. Microscopic particles are in many places at once, but if we look, they appear in only one of these places. This choice of position then affects the future motion of the particle. So the critical question is: what counts as looking?
The branch of quantum mechanics that tries to pin this down is called “decoherence”. I tried reading about decoherence and it went way over my head. There was a lot of math. After five minutes of absolute confusion, I gave up and watched a YouTube video:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gAjzH0vWSIA
Flying fish! How cool is that?
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)