1. Introduction
Why does biological evolution move "forward" in time, despite the fact that the fundamental laws of nature seem to be more or less time-symmetrical? Why are we born before we die, and not after?
Physicists and philosophers often seem to assume that all, or almost all time-asymmetrical (or, irreversible) processes can be reduced to, or explained by, the Second Law of Thermodynamics. In this essay, I will argue that, the biological arrow of time may not be reducible in any straightforward manner to the thermodynamic arrow of time, and that we may need a new cosmological/thermodynamic explanatory framework.
2. The Limits of Thermodynamics
Evolution enables the emergence of more complex beings over time, which, in and of themselves, have relatively low entropy. This doesn't violate the second law, because "mother nature" pays for the reduced local entropy by compensating for it in other ways, like infrared radiation.
That explains how forward evolution is possible despite the second law. That's a far cry from invoking the second law to explain why backwards evolution is impossible!
For evolution to go "forward" in time, it would seem that it needs to go thermodynamically "uphill". Wouldn't it be easier to go downhill? If it was going downhill, then, in principle, it wouldn't need to bother with the infrared radiation, because there would be nothing to compensate for.
3. Niwrad's Universe
Let me introduce you to Niwrad's universe, which I just made up: the universe in which everything else is the same as ours, except biological evolution runs in the opposite time direction. In Niwrad's universe, human beings assemble themselves over a period of years, say, in the ground, and, when they're ready, they're raised from their graves, taken somewhere to come to life, and walk away. Then they get younger until they turn into babies, and the doctors put them into their mothers' wombs.
Something seems wrong with that picture -- but what, really, is the problem? Is the second law of thermodynamics somehow being violated? Let's focus on reverse-decomposition, which is equivalent to spontaneous assembly. Does it violate the second law? No, it doesn't, for the simple reason that, although spontaneous assembly decreases local entropy, mother nature is compensating for it elsewhere. How does mother nature do it? Who knows, that's beside the point. The second law certainly doesn't care. All you have to do to placate the Entropy Police is to pay for the entropy you use. There are no requirements on how you pay.
In fact, the local entropy loss generated by spontaneous assembly is approximately the same entropy loss that happens when a man and a woman have a child (in our universe) -- and mother nature pays for it. How? The second law doesn't care.
So let's put the second law aside for a moment. (Put the second law aside? How could we? That's against the rules! You can't put the second law aside, even for a moment! The second law explains everything! Or maybe it doesn't?) This process still seems astronomically improbable. It should never happen in a million years. And in Niwrad's universe it's happening all over the world all the time.
Does that explain what's wrong with Niwrad's Universe? It certainly seems like it should, but that's just because of our forward-centric bias. After all, look at our own universe.
4. Darwin's Universe
In our own universe, we tend to think that spontaneous assembly doesn't happen, but it all depends on your point of view. If you look at our universe from the other direction of time, "backwards", then spontaneous assembly is happening all over the world, all the time. That's not fair! Why is it OK for astronomically improbable events to happen if you look at our world backwards, but not if you look at our world forwards? Can this somehow be reduced to the second law of thermodynamics? (Hint: it can't.)
We could generalize by saying that in forward-directed time, improbable things rarely happen, and astronomically improbable things approximately never happen, whereas in backwards-directed time, improbable things happen all the time. And this is *not* reducible to the second law of thermodynamics. With apologies to all the real physicists, I'm going call this the first law of chronodynamics, just so that I'll be able to refer to it later.
So we established that, in the backwards direction of time, astronomically improbable things are happening all the time. But not just any random astronomically improbable things. More specifically, in backwards time, astronomically improbable things happen *only if* they *are* probable in the forwards direction. Let's call that the second law of chronodynamics.
Both of these laws seem to be true in our universe. But why? What is really going on?
5. Did the Big Bang Really Have Low Entropy?
The consensus among physicists seems to be that the early universe had (improbably) low entropy. This would seem to be an inescapable consequence of the second law of thermodynamics. After all, if entropy rises with time, then the universe in the past must have had lower entropy than the universe of today -- there's no getting around that. And almost by definition, low entropy is improbable, certainly more improbable than high entropy.
However, I believe that the early universe actually had high entropy -- so high that it was actually at equilibrium. How is that possible? Because the early universe was smaller than the current universe -- not just a bit smaller but way, way smaller. A smaller universe means fewer places particles can be -- smaller positional "phase space", if I'm using the term correctly.
The argument can be found here: https://mccomplete.blogspot.com/2025/03/did-big-bang-really-have-low-entropy.html
6. Macrostate Transitions and Explanation
Take a snapshot of the universe (our universe) at some moment of time, T -- say, 1 billion years ago, with life already flourishing on Earth. This macrostate is far from equilibrium — full of complex structures, gradients, and processes like evolution and metabolism.
If you take the forward-looking view, the macrostate at time T follows -- is caused by -- the macrostate at T - 1. The macrostate transition from T - 1 to T is a "probable" transition, whereas the macrostate transition from T to T - 1 is an improbable transition.
The macrostate transition from T - 1 to T is a "probable" transition, even though neither T - 1 is or T is a probable macrostate. Both T and T - 1 are not at thermodynamic equilibrium -- maximum entropy -- far from it, and therefore, they are both improbable, in and of themselves.
The macrostate at T is an "improbable" macrostate -- unless you *explain* it by invoking the macrostate at T - 1. But that kind of explanation just "begs the question". It pushes the "question" back to T - 1.
But the improbability of T - 1 can be "explained" by invoking T - 2. And so on, back to the big bang.
That's where the high entropy big bang comes in. According to my argument referenced above, the big bang *was* at equilibrium. It was a *probable* macrostate, so it needs no explanation. (What does need explanation is the cosmological arrow of time, the expanding universe.)
7. Conclusion
I have argued that the biological arrow of time is traceable to a boundary condition in the past, but contrary to the standard view, it is traceable to a high entropy -- in fact, equilibrium -- boundary condition, not a low entropy boundary condition.
Due to the fact that the big bang was at equilibrium, relative to its small size, it was able to "kick off" a chain of moments where each moment explains the next -- but only in the forward direction of time.